On the symmetries of electrodynamic interactions
Abstract
While mechanics was developed under the idea of reciprocal action (interactions), electromagnetism, as we know it today, takes a form more akin to unilateral action. Interactions call for spatial relations, unilateral action calls for space, just one reference centre. In contrast, interactions are matters of relations that require at least two centres. The development of the relational electromagnetism encouraged by Gauss appears to stop around 1870 for reasons that are not completely clear but are certainly not solely scientific. By the same time, Maxwell recognised the equivalence in formulae of his electromagnetism and the one advocated by Gauss and called for an explanation of why such theories so differently conceived have such a large part in common. In this work we reconstruct and update the relational electromagnetism up to the contributions of Lorentz guided by the non-arbitrariness principle (NAP) that requests arbitrary choices to be accompanied by groups of symmetries. We show that a-priori there must be two more symmetries in electromagnetism, one related to the breaking (in the description) of the relation source/detector and one relating all the perceptions of the same source by detectors moving with different (constant) relative velocities. We show that the idea of electromagnetic waves put forward in concept by Lorenz (1861-1863) before Maxwell (1865) and in formulae (1867) just after Maxwell, together with the ``least action principle'' proposed by Lorentz are enough to derive Maxwell's equations, the continuity equation and the Lorentz' force, and that there is a dual formulation in terms of fields of the receiver (as opposed to fields of the source). While Galilean transformations are associated with removing the arbitrariness implied in the election of a reference space, they will not explicitly appear in a formulation based upon a relational space although we occasionally mention their usefulness. In contrast, Lorentz' transformations will emerge in this formulation involving the relations between the perceived fields of different receivers. Moreover, the role of the full Poincaré-Lorentz group as a group of transformations of the perceived actions is elucidated. In summary, we answer Maxwell's philosophical question showing how the same theory in formulae can be abduced using different inferred entities. Each form of abduction implies as well an interpretation and a facilitation of the theoretical construction. This work relies heavily on logical concepts as abduction put forward by C. Peirce, needed for the construction of theories.
Keywords
Full Text:
PDFReferences
V I Arnold. Mathematical Methods of Classical Mechanics. 2nd edition. Springer, New York, 1989. 1st edition 1978.
Frederick C Beiser. After Hegel. Princeton University Press, 2014.
Enrico Betti. Sopra la elettrodinamica. Il Nuovo Cimento (1855-1868), 27 (1): 402–407, 1867.
Chuang Tzu. The complete works of Chuang Tzu. Columbia University Press, 1968. ISBN 0-231-03147-5.
R Clausius. Lxii. upon the new conception of electrodynamic phenomena suggested by gauss. The London, Edinburgh, and Dublin Philosophical Magazine and Journal of Science, 37 (251): 445–456, 1869.
Herbert Dingle. The doppler effect and the foundations of physics (i). The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 11 (41): 11–31, 1960.
Michael Faraday. Experimentl Researches in Electricity (Vol I). Richard and John Edward Taylor, 1839.
Michael Faraday. Experimentl Researches in Electricity (Vol II). Richard Taylor and William Francis, 1844.
Michael Faraday. Experimentl Researches in Electricity (Vol III). Richard and John Edward Taylor, 1855.
Carl Friedrich Gauss. Carl Friedrich Gauss, Werke, volume 5. K. Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften zu Göttingen, 1870. Digitizing sponsor University of California Libraries.
R Gilmore. Lie Groups, Lie Algebras, and Some of Their Applications. Wiley, New York, 1974.
M Hamermesh. Groups Theory and its Application to Physical Problems. Addison Wesley, Reading, MA, 1962.
Oliver Heaviside. Electrical papers, volume 2. Cambridge University Press (1894), 2011. Digitized by Google.
H Hertz. Electric waves. MacMillan and Co, 1893. Translated by D E Jones with a preface by Lord Kevin.
Christa Jungnickel and Russell McCormmach. The Second Physicist (On the History of Theoretical Physics in Germany), volume 48 of Archimedes. Springer, 2017.
Matti Kaivola, Ove Poulsen, Erling Riis, and Siu Au Lee. Measurement of the relativistic doppler shift in neon. Physical review letters, 54 (4): 255, 1985.
Immanuel Kant. The Critique of Pure Reason. An Electronic Classics Series Publication, 1787. translated by J. M. D. Meiklejohn.
Immanuel Kant. The conflict of the faculties (the contest of the faculties). Der Streit der Fakultäten. Hans Reiss, ed., Kant: Political Writings, 2d ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 1798. URL la.utexas.edu/users/hcleaver/330T/350kPEEKantConflictFacNarrow.pdf.
H A Lorentz. La théorie Électromagnétique de maxwell et son application aux corps mouvants. Archives Néerlandaises des Sciences exactes et naturelles, XXV: 363–551, 1892. URL https://www.biodiversitylibrary.org/item/181480#page/417/mode/1up. Scanned by Biodiversity Heritage Library from holding at Harvard University Botany Libraries.
L Lorenz. Xlix. on the determination of the direction of the vibrations of polarized light by means of diffraction. The London, Edinburgh, and Dublin Philosophical Magazine and Journal of Science, 21 (141): 321–331, 1861.
Ludvig Lorenz. Xii. on the theory of light. The London, Edinburgh, and Dublin Philosophical Magazine and Journal of Science, 26 (173): 81–93, 1863.
Ludvig Lorenz. Xxxviii. on the identity of the vibrations of light with electrical currents. The London, Edinburgh, and Dublin Philosophical Magazine and Journal of Science, 34 (230): 287–301, 1867.
Hirsch I Mandelberg and Louis Witten. Experimental verification of the relativistic doppler effect. JOSA, 52 (5): 529–535, 1962.
James Clerk Maxwell. A dynamical theory of the electromagnetic field. Proceedings of the Royal Society (United Kingdom), 1865.
James Clerk Maxwell. A Treatise on Electricity and Magnetism, volume 1 and 2. Dover (1954), 1873.
James Clerk Maxwell. The Scientific Letters and Papers of James Clerk Maxwell: Volume 1, 1846-1862, volume 1. CUP Archive, 1990.
MA Natiello and HG Solari. Relational electromagnetism and the electromagnetic force, 2021. URL https://arxiv.org/pdf/2102.13108.
C. Neumann. Die principien der elektrodynamik. Eine mathematische Untersuchung. Verlag der Lauppschen Buchhandlung, Tübingen, 1868. Reprinted in Mathematischen Annalen, Vol. 17, pp. 400 - 434 (1880).
FE Neumann. Allgemeine gesetze der inducierten elektrischen strome. pogg. Annalen der Physik (Poggendorf), 143(1): 31–44, 1846.
Isaac Newton. Philosophiæ naturalis principia mathematica (“Mathematical principles of natural philosophy”). London, 1687. Consulted: Motte translation (1723) published by Daniel Adee publisher (1846). And the Motte translation revised by Florian Cajori (1934) published by Univ of California Press (1999).
Charles Peirce. The Philosophical Writings of Peirce. Dover Publications, 1955. Selected and edited by Justus Buchler.
Charles Peirce. Collected papers of charles sanders peirce. Charlottesville, Va.: InteLex Corporation,, electronic edition edition, 1994.
Jean Piaget. The Construction Of Reality In The Child. International Library of Psychology. Routledge, 1999. ISBN 0415210003,9780415210003.
H Poincaré. The theory of lorentz and the principle of reaction. Archives Néerlandaises des sciences exactes et naturelles, 5: 252–278, 1900.
H Poincaré. Science and Hypothesis. The foundations of science. The science press, 1913. Translated by George B Halsted.
B. Riemann. Xlvii. a contribution to electrodynamics. The London, Edinburgh, and Dublin Philosophical Magazine and Journal of Science, 34 (231): 368––372, 1867. Translated from Poggendorff’s Annalen, No. 6, 1867. Laid before the Royal Society of Sciences at Göttingen on the 10th of February 1858. Published posthumous.
Ludwik Silberstein. The theory of relativity. Macmillan, 2nd edition, 1924 edition, 1914.
H G Solari and M A Natiello. A constructivist view of newton’s mechanics. Foundations of Science, 24:307, 2018. URL https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-018-9573-z.
H. G. Solari and M. A. Natiello. On the relation of free bodies, inertial sets and arbitrariness. Science & Philosophy, 9 (2): 7–26, 2021. ISSN 2282-7757, eISSN 2282-7765. URL http://eiris.it/ojs/index.php/scienceandphilosophy/article/view/669/851.
H G Solari and M A Natiello. A critical assessment of scientific retroduction. . URL https://philpapers.org/rec/SOLACA-2.
H. G. Solari and Mario Natiello. Science, dualities and the fenomenological map. Foundations of Science, 2022b. URL https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-022-09850-4.
Paul R Thagard. The best explanation: Criteria for theory choice. The journal of philosophy, 75 (2): 76–92, 1978.
James Thomson. On the law of inertia; the principle of chronometry; and the principle of absolute clinural rest, and of absolute rotation. Proceedings of the Royal Society of Edinburgh, 12: 568–578, 1884.
Wilhelm Weber. Determinations of electromagnetic meassure; concerning a universal law of electrical action. Prince Jablonowski Society (Leipzig), pages 211–378, 1846. Translated by Susan P. Johnson and edited by Laurence Hecht and A. K. T. Assis from Wilhelm Weber, Elektrodynamische Maassbestimmungen: Ueber ein allgemeines Grundgesetz der elektrischen Wirkung, Werke, Vol. III: Galvanismus und Electrodynamik, part 1, edited by
H. Weber (Berlin: Julius Springer Verlag, 1893), pp. 25-214.
William Whewell. The philosophy of the inductive sciences, volume 1. JW Parker, 1840.
William Whewell. The history of scientific ideas, volume 1. JW Parker, 1858a. Third Edition.
William Whewell. Novum organon renovastrum. JW Parker, 1858b. Being the second part of The philosophy of Inductive sciences. Third edition.
DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.23756/sp.v10i2.811
Refbacks
- There are currently no refbacks.
Copyright (c) 2022 Hernán Gustavo Solari, Mario Alberto Natiello
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.
Science & Philosophy - Journal of Epistemology, Science and Philosophy. ISSN 2282-7757; eISSN 2282-7765.